People like to see things in black and white. It allows one
to abstract from complexities and nuances, and thus sort real-world phenomena
into neatly demarcated categories that make those phenomena more comprehensible
or more consonant with preconceptions. Nowhere is this tendency more apparent
than the Cold-War dichotomy between capitalism and communism. While the
dichotomy is obviously useful, it clearly doesn’t tell the whole story – there are
elements of central planning and socialism even in capitalist economies, just as
there are elements of private enterprise and market competition even in
communist economies. In other words, economic systems do not conform to pure
ideal-types in reality.
An interesting way to see this is to ask where cooperatives
fit in the schema – are they a form of capitalism or communism, or do they
instead represent some sort of ‘third way’ such as market socialism? All three of
the possible responses can be found. Because capitalism is today the dominant
economic system, however, the question is usually formulated as: do
cooperatives represent an alternative to capitalism (be it communism or a ‘third
way’) or merely a certain type of capitalism? I have found that the first option
is the most commonly held – most people instinctively associate cooperatives with a non-capitalist, even communist, mode of production. This makes sense if one defines capitalism as an
economic system in which capital hires labour (or owns it, if slavery is not
abolished), given that in a cooperative labour owns capital (or hires it, as in
a usufruct arrangement). After all, how can there be capitalism without
capitalists?
This very logic is evident in the political economy of Karl
Marx, who stated that cooperatives “have shown that production on a large
scale, and in accord with the behests of modern science, may be carried on
without the existence of a class of masters employing a class of hands…and
that, like slave labor, like serf labor, hired labor is but a transitory and
inferior form, destined to disappear before associated labour…” (Marx 1864,
para. 13). Engels (1989 [1880]: 43) likewise opined that cooperatives have
“given practical proof that the merchant and the manufacturer are socially
quite unnecessary”. In other words, cooperatives “represent within the old form
the first sprouts of the new” (Marx 1959 [1894], Chapter 27, para. 17). Indeed, in
his ‘New Economy Policy’, Lenin envisaged cooperatives as a bridge to communism.
In the same breath as praising cooperatives, however, Marx (1867,
Section 5, para. 3; 1970 [1875]) – along with his adherents and other radicals –
not only belittled, but also severely scorned them. The concern is that
cooperatives, far from representing a “transforming force” (Marx 1867, Section
5, para. 2), may amount to a sort of ‘false dawn’ that actually ends up
impeding the revolution. By replacing class identity with organisational
loyalty and even eliminating class distinction within the enterprise altogether,
cooperatives may perpetuate “false consciousness” and obviate the role of trade
unions, even while their members voluntarily endure alienating work conditions
and exploitative management systems (see Paranque and Willmott 2014). In short,
the criticism is that cooperatives represent a palliative sugar-coating to
capitalism rather than a radical alternative; and in response to the question
of ‘how can there be capitalism without capitalists?’, radical critics of
cooperatives contend that worker-members essentially act as “their own capitalists”
(Jossa 2005: 14).
Alas, I am not a (out-and-out) Marxist. In my view, the
objective should not be to eradicate capitalism, but rather to harness its
organisational power, competitive drive, and technological dynamism while
avoiding its tendency towards financialisation and crisis, exacerbation of
inequality, preservation of unemployment, stimulation of anomie/alienation, environmental
degradation, and so on [1]. That is to say, we need to reap the productive benefits
of capitalism, which Marx himself extolled, while moderating its adverse
socio-economic effects, which Marx predicted would cause it to self-destruct. In
this sense, I see cooperatives as conservative, or at least reformative, and
even anti-revolutionary.
There is an important question, however, as to whether
capitalism’s benefits can be enjoyed, and its adverse effects avoided, in a
situation where capital does not hire labour – can cooperatives have their cake
and eat it too? According to many radicals, islands of cooperative labour in a
sea of capitalist relations - "small units of socialised production within capitalist exchange", as Rosa Luxemburg (1986
[1900]), para. 3) put it - will tend to do just the opposite; by struggling to survive and eventually ‘degenerating’ into capitalist firms (see Egan
1990), while in the meantime “reproduc[ing]…all the shortcomings of the prevailing
system” (Marx 1959 [1894], Chapter 27, para. 17), they will instead combine 'the worst of both worlds'.
What would happen, though, if cooperatives were scaled up to the entire (or a significant proportion of) the economy? The answer to this question brings us full circle to the question of whether a cooperative economy would/could be capitalism. As I implied earlier, this is largely a matter of semantics: if by ‘capitalism’ you mean ‘a system in which capital hires labour’, then the answer is no – qualified, of course, by the ‘self-exploitation’ critique. Marx (1864, para. 14) believed that “co-operative labor…fostered by national means” and “developed to national dimensions” could bring about true and lasting “emancipation of labor”. In an earlier blog, however, I argued that a cooperative economy would not necessarily be communism. In fact, as per Lenin’s New Economic Policy, Marx seems to have had in mind some sort of transitional mode of production that would eventually herald full-blown communism. Conversely, cooperatives have often proliferated in countries ‘opening up’ to the internal and external markets, such as today’s Cuba under Raul Castro. So it seems that a cooperative economy would indeed be some sort of 'third way', defying the crude dichotomy between capitalism and communism. For me, the really interesting question is therefore whether such an alternative economy is an inherently transitory one, or whether it can represent a more permanent socio-economic system.
What would happen, though, if cooperatives were scaled up to the entire (or a significant proportion of) the economy? The answer to this question brings us full circle to the question of whether a cooperative economy would/could be capitalism. As I implied earlier, this is largely a matter of semantics: if by ‘capitalism’ you mean ‘a system in which capital hires labour’, then the answer is no – qualified, of course, by the ‘self-exploitation’ critique. Marx (1864, para. 14) believed that “co-operative labor…fostered by national means” and “developed to national dimensions” could bring about true and lasting “emancipation of labor”. In an earlier blog, however, I argued that a cooperative economy would not necessarily be communism. In fact, as per Lenin’s New Economic Policy, Marx seems to have had in mind some sort of transitional mode of production that would eventually herald full-blown communism. Conversely, cooperatives have often proliferated in countries ‘opening up’ to the internal and external markets, such as today’s Cuba under Raul Castro. So it seems that a cooperative economy would indeed be some sort of 'third way', defying the crude dichotomy between capitalism and communism. For me, the really interesting question is therefore whether such an alternative economy is an inherently transitory one, or whether it can represent a more permanent socio-economic system.
Notes
[1] It might be (validly) argued that economic growth is no
longer necessary, desirable, or even feasible in advanced economies, and that
we are currently suffering from all of capitalism’s ills while its benefits
either fail to materialise or fail to improve actual living standards. Be that
as it may, economic growth is certainly still required in most countries, and
even in advanced economies, innovations and increases in efficiency will
still be required in order to maintain current standards of living, for
instance due to the eventual depletion of natural resources.
References
- Egan, D. (1990). Toward a Marxist Theory of Labor-Managed Firms: Breaking the Degeneration Thesis. Review of Radical Political Economics, 22(4), 67–86.
- Engels, F. (1989 [1880]) Socialism: Utopian and Scientific. In Marx-Engels Collected Works (Vol. 24, pp. 281–325). New York: International.
- Jossa, B. (2005). Marx, Marxism and the Cooperative Movement. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 29(1), 3–18.
- Luxemburg, R. (1986 [1900]). Reform or Revolution (London: Militant Publishers), Chapter 7, accessed at https://www.marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1900/reform-revolution/index.htm
- Marx, K. (1864). Inaugural Address and Provisional Rules of the International Working Men’s Association, along with the “General Rules.” London: International Working Men’s Association. Retrieved from https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1864/10/27.htm
- Marx, K. (1867). Instructions for the Delegates of the Provisional General Council. The International Courier, 6/7. Retrieved from https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1866/08/instructions.htm#05
- Marx, K. (1959 [1894]). Capital, Volume III. (Marx, K. & Engels, F., Eds.). New York: International. Retrieved from http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1894-c3/
- Marx, K. (1970 [1875]). Critique of the Gotha Programme. Moscow, Russia: Progress. Retrieved from https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1875/gotha/index.htm
- Paranque, B., & Willmott, H. C. (2014). Cooperatives - Saviors or Gravediggers of Capitalism? Critical Performativity and the John Lewis Partnership. Organization, 21(5), 604–625.
No comments:
Post a Comment